ROBIN COLLINS, Ph.D.
DISTINGUISHED PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY AND CHAIR OF THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY
Professor Robin Collins, Ph.D., is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Chair of the Department of Philosophy. He specializes in philosophy of science, philosophy of religion, metaphysics, and philosophical theology. He is well-versed in issues relating to science and religion, with graduate-level training in theoretical physics. He has written almost forty substantial articles and book chapters in these areas with some of the leading academic presses, such as Oxford University Press, Cambridge University Press, Blackwell, and Routledge. He has also spoken on issues relating to God and the cosmos at many colleges and universities (including Oxford University, Cambridge University, Yale University, and Stanford University) and has appeared in the popular Christian and secular media – for example, in Christianity Today, Lee Strobel’s Case for the Creator, and Robert Kuhn’s PBS series Closer to the Truth. Professor Collins is widely regarded as the foremost expert on the fine-tuning argument, an argument for the existence of God based on the extraordinarily precise structure that the universe must have for life to exist. He is currently finishing two books on this topic: one that provides a detailed analysis of the evidence for fine-tuning and one that carefully makes the philosophical case from fine-tuning to divine creation. Besides his work on fine- tuning, he has written on the philosophy of quantum mechanics, the relation between the mind and the body, the nature of prayer, atonement, and a variety of other topics in philosophy of
science and philosophy of religion.
God as the Ultimate Explanation of the Universe’s Order
ROBIN COLLINS, Ph.D.
I have several reasons for believing in God, the most important being that theism can plausibly explain the universe’s underlying simple, elegant, and discoverable mathematical order and its fine-tuning for life.(1) Without further explanation, having such an order strikes many as an enormous cosmic coincidence, and hence highly implausible. This is because we judge that there are vastly more ways in which the universe’s mass/energy could be ordered that would be far less significant. (2) Further, if we really believed this order was just a brute fact (i.e., had no further explanation), then we should not expect the order to continue, contrary to what everyone does.(3)
Despite recognizing the initial seemingly enormous implausibility of considering this order a brute fact, many atheists respond that invoking a divine mind to explain this order involves hypothesizing something whose existence is just as coincidental as that of the order of the universe.(4) I believe atheists are right if one thinks of God anthropomorphically like a super version of a human mind, with all the organized complexity necessary for it to function. However, I believe that grounding theism in the claim that consciousness is at the foundation of reality avoids this coincidence. A sketch of my reasoning goes as follows:
Either consciousness, the not-conscious, or a combination of the two is fundamental.(5)
Since there are only three possibilities and consciousness being fundamental seems aslikely as the two other possibilities, consciousness being fundamental is not coincidental.(6)
Assume consciousness and agency go together, implying that consciousness and agencyare jointly fundamental. (I define “agency” as the ability to give being (actuality) to amental representation of a state of affairs.)
Since this consciousness/agency is fundamental, it follows that it is not limited byanything external. Assuming it also has no internal limitations,(7) it follows that it has no limitations whatsoever.
Unlimited consciousness would contain representations of every possible reality;(8) andunlimited agency could actualize any such representation.(9)
Assume the widely-held thesis going back to Plato that goodness and beauty areintrinsically self-motivating: i.e., a person’s perceiving a state of affairs as good orbeautiful gives them some reason to bring it about.
As noted above, the universe’s order exhibits certain unique kinds of beauty andelegance; further, by permitting the existence of embodied moral agents, it allows forunique types of moral goods.(10)
Therefore, by #6 and #7 above, this unlimited consciousness/agency – which I define as God- has a reason to actualize a universe like ours, making it not highly coincidental that God would do so.
In my judgment, none of the above steps require hypothesizing a major coincidence or implausibility. Hence, I believe the theistic explanation is not highly implausible, making it far superior to the brute fact explanation. Finally, to complete the case for God, elsewhere I argue that other naturalistic attempts to explain this order do little better than the brute
fact hypothesis.(11)
Footnotes:
1. The order I am thinking of here is that expressed by the most fundamental theories and equations of physics. Many leading physicists have recognized each of the above features of this order. For example, Nobel laureate (and atheist) Steven Weinberg, has noted how this perceived beauty has guided physicists in choosing the correct equations. (See his Dreams of a Final Theory. New York: Vintage Books, 1994, Chapter 6, “Beautiful Theories.”) Weinberg even admits that “sometimes nature seems more beautiful than strictly necessary” (1992, p. 250). Concerning the universe’s discoverability and intelligibility, Albert Einstein famously remarked that “the most incomprehensible thing about the world is that it is comprehensible.” (“Physics and Reality.” Journal of the Franklin Institute, 221(3), 1936): 349-382.) Similarly, Eugene Wigner, one of the major founders of quantum mechanics, wrote in an often-cited essay that our ability to successfully use mathematics to uncover the order of nature borders on the miraculous. (“The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences.” Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13(1), 1960: 1-14.) Finally, the fine-tuning of the cosmos for life refers to the fact that the basic structure of the cosmos must be set to an enormous degree of precision for life to occur. This has received much discussion in the past forty years. For the most up-to-date discussion of this fine-tuning, see Barnes, Luke, and Geraint Lewis. 2016. A Fortunate Universe: Life in a Finely Tuned Cosmos. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. For a popular presentation, see my “The Case for Cosmic Design,” in Paul Draper, editor, God or Blind Nature?: Philosopher’s Debate the Evidence (2007-2008), at https://infidels.org/library/modern/robin-collins-design. Finally, for a sophisticated account of how it supports theism, see my “The Teleological Argument: An Exploration of the Fine-Tuning of the Universe.” William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland, ed. The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009, pp. 202–28.
2. Even many who believe the fundamental order is a brute fact, such as Norman Swartz, recognize that it seems to be an enormous cosmic coincidence. (See his The Concept of Physical Law, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 1985, pp. 203- 204.) However, they claim that alternative explanations either are incoherent or involve hypothesizing their own cosmic coincidence: as Swartz puts it, “at some point, we have our backs to the wall.” (Ibid., p. 204). Other philosophers find the brute fact hypothesis completely unacceptable. For example, non-theist philosopher David Armstrong claims that “if you believe that, you will believe anything.” (See David Armstrong, “Reply to Van Fraassen,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 66, No. 2 (June 1988): 229.)
3. A coin’s landing on heads ten times in a row only gives us reason to believe it will land on heads the eleventh time if we believe there was some reason for this occurrence, such as that it was weighted in favor of heads.
4. For example, this is Richard Dawkins’ main objection to design arguments. (See Dawkins, Richard. 1986. The Blind Watchmaker. New York, NY: W. W. Norton and Co., p. 316.) This criticism goes back to the famous Scottish philosopher David Hume (1711 - 1776), who stated that that “there is no more difficulty conceiving that the several elements [of nature], from an internal unknown cause, may fall into the most exquisite arrangement, than to conceive that their ideas, in the great universal mind, from a like unknown cause, fall into that arrangement.” (See Hume, David. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. 2nd edition. Edited by Richard Popkin: Indianapolis, PA: Hackett Publishing Company, 1980, pp. 17-18.)
5. I define a fundamental reality as a reality such that all other realities – except perhaps abstract realities, such as mathematical truths – depend on it, while it depends on nothing else.
6. To clarify, it would only be coincidental if there were many, many other alternatives that we judged as equally good candidates for being fundamental, or if something about consciousness being fundamental made it intrinsically highly unlikely. Neither of these seems to be the case.
7. An example of the kind of internal limitation I have in mind is one in which as a brute fact or some hidden metaphysical necessity, God cannot create some otherwise seemingly possible state of affairs, such as a world with unicorns.
8. Such representations are what philosophers call possible worlds. Many philosophers – whether theist or non-theist – postulate the existence of possible worlds to account for the logic of statements regarding possibility and necessity (modal logic). Further, almost all of them hold that such worlds exist by metaphysical necessity, just as mathematical platonists do regarding mathematical truths. So, it is plausible to think the existence of such possible worlds is not coincidental.
9. To keep things simple, I ignore here the existence of libertarian free-willed creatures whose choices God cannot actualize.
10. For example, embodiment permits persons to be vulnerable to others and their environment, thereby allowing for such moral goods as sacrificially helping others in a natural disaster. (I elaborate on the eternal value of such goods in my essay, “The Connection Building Theodicy.” The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil, Dan Howard-Snyder and Justin McBrayer, eds., Malden, MA: Wiley- Blackwell, 2014, pp. 222-235.)
11. At the core of the theistic explanation is the independently plausible principle that goodness and beauty are self-motivating. Via God, this principle favors the existence of realities that instantiate goodness and beauty, as arguably the order of this universe does. The challenge for naturalistic accounts is finding a non-arbitrary principle that favors the kind of order in our universe over the seemingly much vaster array of alternatives. I analyze this issue in much more detail in my "God and the Laws of Nature." Philo: A Journal of Philosophy, 12(2), 2009: 142–171. In that article, I consider other potential alternative explanations, three of which I briefly address here. For example, one might appeal to some underlying metaphysical necessity. However, I argue that this merely transfers the coincidence to why these necessities are such as to give rise to the kind of order in our universe instead of one of the vast number of other possibilities that seem far less significant. Another possibility is to claim that only universes with such order could allow for observers; hence, it is no coincidence (when combined with a multiverse hypothesis) that we find ourselves in such a universe. One major problem with this explanation is that such observers only require highly local regions of order, and hence we would not expect such order to continue in the future or exist in other parts of the universe. It also does not account for the discoverability or elegance of the laws of nature. Another potential explanation is a metaphysical or epistemological principle of simplicity according to which simple patterns are more probable than complex patterns. A major problem with this idea, however, is that under it we would expect the universe to be far simpler than it is, e.g., two particles traveling through empty space at a constant velocity relative to each other.